logo

44 pages 1 hour read

Friedrich Engels

The Origin of the Family, Private Property and the State

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 1884

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Chapter 8-Addendum Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Chapter 8 Summary: “The Formation of the State Among the Germans”

Tacitus describes the Germans as having a massive population, which must have continued to grow as they formed settlements. As they grew, they pressed their attacks on the increasingly hapless Romans, but before the Romans collapsed, they had already wreaked havoc on the whole of European civilization, having “everywhere broken up the old kinship groups and with them the last vestige of local and national independence” (184). The only institution capable of binding people into something resembling nations was the Roman state, but that state had so thoroughly mismanaged affairs for so long that there was a general collapse of all society beyond the local level. Many enslaved people were freed because nobody could afford to support them, even as many legally free people found themselves in a condition much like slavery. The German conquerors of Rome tried to reallocate property on the basis of gens, but nothing could change the fact that they were conquerors, and “rule over subjugated peoples is incompatible with the gentile constitution” (188). The best they could do was replace one state with another, and they did so by turning their military leaders into kings. Territory became the property of the monarch, under the supervision of his personal retinue of soldiers. This system proved so destabilizing and violent that it weakened itself just as the Romans had weakened themselves, ultimately leaving the Germans exposed to Viking raiders who retained a vestige of the old gens-based system. Just like the Romans, the Germans’ reliance on large landowners and urban centers of government sapped the people of freedom, so that the only remaining free institutions were Christian monasteries whose inhabitants could neither reproduce nor offer an effective defense against outsiders.

For all its tragedies, this period was not without its benefits. The old traces of German civilization were strong enough to secure Europe against Norse and Islamic invaders and to preserve the merest trace of individual freedom and female equality in a culture otherwise hostile to both. Most importantly, “they were able to develop and make universal the milder form of servitude they had practiced in their own country...[which] gives to the bondsmen the means of their gradual liberation as a class” (193), planting seeds which would many centuries later help liberate medieval serfs, with hope for the modern proletariat.

Chapter 9 Summary: “Barbarism and Civilization”

Engels reviews his findings, beginning with a summary of the “middle stage of savagery” (195), where the gens manages its own affairs and there is “no place for ruler and ruled” (195). All of humanity enjoyed this condition at one point or another but moved out of it at various stages based on the domestication of animals, the development of tools, and advancements in agriculture. It is not always clear how the transition from common possession among the gens to private ownership among families occurred, but occur it did. Once marriage became a means of organizing property, men became ascendant and women themselves became a kind of property, kept within the home to attend to domestic labor. The rule of men within the house then paved the way for tyranny over society as a whole, with iron serving as a far more effective weapon of conquest than the stone used by earlier peoples. Conquest and expansion led to larger populations, which then exacerbated differences between rich and poor, and those who were once temporary military leaders became hereditary monarchs as a way to preserve their privileges against the potentially restive masses. They then engaged in wars of conquest to enrich themselves further, even as these led to even greater social instability requiring even greater concentrations of wealth and power.

This process precedes the rise of what Engels, following Morgan’s taxonomy, calls “civilization,” the chief characteristic of which is the division of labor (202). In addition to differences between rich and poor, town and country, civilization “creates a class which no longer concerns itself with production, but only with the exchange of the products—the merchants” (203). These people enrich themselves despite having nothing at all to do with production, introducing money as the key variable of exchange and with it the relationship between debtor and creditor. The gentile constitution could not long survive this state of affairs and was gradually relegated to the private sphere. In its place came the state, and while traces of the old gentile constitution remained, class antagonism became the main feature of society, which the state handled by organizing power on a territorial basis, organizing a public force of agents for maintaining order, especially against a large enslaved population, and extracting taxes from citizens. This creates organs of power “standing above society” (209), interested mainly in preserving rights of property. Modern democracies continue this trend by formalizing class conflict within legislative assemblies, while the real power is in the “alliance between the government and the stock exchange” (211). Once goods become commodities, they separate the producer from their product, which is symbolic of a broader alienation between human beings and their natural environment. By developing “things of which gentile society was not even remotely capable,” civilization set “in motion the lowest instincts and passions of men” who turned on each other to satisfy limitless greed (215). The development of civilization has been the death of genuine society.

Addendum Summary: “A Recently Discovered Case of Group Marriage”

A recent meeting of the Anthropological Section of the Society of the Friends of Natural Science found a case of group marriage among the Gilyaks (or Nivkh, an Indigenous group inhabiting parts of coastal Siberia) who still practice it in the present day. They were able to sustain this arrangement by maintaining a strictly hunting and gathering lifestyle, with no industry or agriculture. Social life takes place entirely within the rules of the gens, and there are neither rich nor poor. Engels characterizes the Gilyak people as kind, hospitable, and free of greed. There is good reason to fear that as they develop contacts with Russia and China, their “changes in fortune” will destroy “more and more that primitive equality” which the modern world destroys with utter ruthlessness (222).

Chapter 8-Addendum Analysis

Once again, Engels flips the script on conventional history. In Engels’s era, the fall of the Roman empire was widely considered one of the great tragedies in history, where the “barbarian” triumph erased culture and learning from Europe for centuries, until the Renaissance was at last able to recover the wisdom of antiquity. In Engels’s telling, the real tragedy is The Conflict Between the Family and the State. The Germans in particular were able to preserve gens-based communities for centuries, even during periods of consistent contact with the Romans. Theirs was not exactly a model society—as a pastoral people, they fought vicious wars for control of grasslands, eventually leading to more permanent military formations and an extensive reliance on slavery. Their rapid population growth suggests a degree of “civilization” that did not derive from the poisonous influence of the Romans, but for that stage of history, they were about as close to Engels’s ideal as could be reasonably expected. Their very ability to vanquish the Romans proved that they retained the old virile spirit of the gens, compared to the inhabitants of a state who vacillate between servility and cruelty. They tried to reorganize Roman territory along gentile lines, distributing land “by lot in equal portions among the individual households” and keeping “woods and pastures undivided for common use” (187-88). Even at this point, leaders were elected and accountable, and thanks to their example, enough of the old gentile spirit would find its way into Europe to at least carry a vestige of resistance as the state eventually took over. Again, this was not some set of “specific national qualities” but the mere fact of “their barbarism, their gentile constitution” which would preserve a legacy of freedom and the hope of its revival over the many centuries to come (192).

Engels argues that the real tragedy is not that the barbarians overcame civilization, but that the barbarians became civilized. In true Marxist fashion, this is a matter of social circumstances, rather than moral decay. The needs of governing the territory they had just conquered left no other alternative than the appropriation of Roman methods, since the Romans had so thoroughly extirpated the social conditions required for anything like a gentile constitution. “Civilization”—meaning an economy based on money and overseen by a ruling class whose primary goal is to preserve its own power—had already triumphed, and so it was fairly easy for it to transition from one set of “masters” to another. Instead, the marriage of Roman and “barbarian” institutions laid the groundwork for feudalism, which then paved the way for capitalism. The final passages bring the book more explicitly in line with familiar modes of Marxist argument, the alienation of the producer from the product, and the veneer of democracy to trick the working classes into thinking they have representation while the real powers operate behind the scenes. Yet this text still stands apart from many other, better-known Marxist tracts, in its explicit linkage of workers’ liberation with female liberation. If the great mistake of human history was The Shift from Matriarchy to Patriarchy, then the heart of unjust power lies in male domination of the home. Once it is possible to “emancipate woman and make her the equal of the man” (199), revolution cannot be far behind.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text