49 pages • 1 hour read
Judith ButlerA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
This chapter focuses on the question of what kind of community can arise out of the vulnerability to violence, loss, and the mourning that ensues. According to Butler, there is no “argument” to made against vulnerability and loss, as these are conditions of life.
In the context of the violence of 9/11 and the United States’ violent response to these attacks, Butler takes up several crucial questions in this chapter: “Who counts as human? Whose lives count as lives? And, finally, What makes for a grievable life?” (20).
Butler approaches vulnerability not only in its individuality, such as the vulnerability of individual bodies, but also in its social context. Humans are constituted politically precisely because they are socially vulnerable. This social vulnerability is grounded in being “socially constituted bodies” (20): People are attached to others and thus risk losing those attachments, and people are exposed to others, and thus at risk of violence because of that exposure.
With loss comes mourning. Freud originally theorized the success of mourning with interchangeability: A severed attachment could simply be replaced by another attachment. Butler acknowledges that they do not know what “successful” mourning is. Rather than a task that one sets out to accomplish, mourning is often overwhelming, as the “transformative effect” of loss cannot be planned and exceeds one’s own agency. If there is any “success” in the process, it may be in “submitting” to the transformative nature of mourning.
If mourning exceeds agency and transforms a person, loss itself is “enigmatic”: People often do not know what they have lost. The enigma of loss not only lies in what is lost, but within the self. In mourning, one becomes “inscrutable” to the self. This inscrutability foregrounds that there is not simply a relation in which individuals or entities exist independent of one another, but there are ties that bind one to another, and these ties “constitute” us as humans, even as we lose them.
While the general approach to mourning is that it is private and “privatizing,” Butler insists again that mourning is political. Mourning foregrounds “relational ties” that articulate dependency and ethical responsibility. If people are constituted by one another and by the ties that are created and lost, this relationality is a fact of existence, and thus existence is undeniably social and political.
This dissolution of bonds in loss results in an unutterable narrative, where one is not sure how to present a first-person account of the self. People are both “in thrall” to one another and “undone” by one another. Continuing with this train of thought, Butler asserts that people are “dispossessed” by mourning and, more broadly, by these ties. They are dispossessed of a clear understanding of these relational ties and themselves.
Butler holds this dispossession up against the claims to individuality and bodily autonomy that are central to many political movements. Butler does not discount the need for these movements or the need for bodily autonomy that they seek. At the same time, this understanding of people as autonomous beings does not fully comprehend humans’ existence. Butler is thus calling for an alternative “normative aspiration” that acknowledges and supports the “dispossession” of relations. People must both struggle for autonomy as well as for a communal existence in which people acknowledge and celebrate our vulnerability and dependence on one another. People are more than discrete, autonomous, “bounded” beings, as their past “primary others” (such as parents) live on in the very fiber of “the boundary that contains me” (28).
Returning to the “opportunity” that violence affords, as discussed in Chapter 1, Butler asks Americans whether there is “something to be learned about the geopolitical distribution of corporeal vulnerability from our own brief and devastating exposure to this condition” (29). Americans’ exposure as a nation is minimal compared to most of the world, which lives in much greater vulnerability. Contrary to the fear of mourning and desire to eradicate it to “return” to “normal” is Butler’s insistence on mourning as a political “resource” in which Americans slowly identify with suffering and an “unknowingness” about the other, ties with the other, and themselves. Grief is disorienting: One no longer has a sense of what “I” am in the face of the loss of the other and may feel as though they don’t know at all who the other was.
This question of vulnerability and loss leads Butler to a discussion of humans whose lives do not register as lives and thus whose deaths do not register as losses. These are lives designated as “unreal.” Those who are considered “unreal” have already, in this very designation, experienced violence. Once life is derealized, “from the perspective of violence, it fails to injure or negate those lives, since those lives are already negated” (33). At the same time, the lives of those who have been derealized are never securely derealized and thus must be negated constantly. This derealization is a state of undeadness, from the perspective of violence, that requires a constant replenishing of violence. This state of undeadness can be witnessed, for example, in the genre of the obituary, where certain deaths are not allowed to be mourned publicly and thus refused mournability.
Butler here offers the example of the San Francisco Chronicle refusing to publish an obituary or even statements “in memoriam” for two Palestinian families killed by Israeli troops on the grounds that publication would “offend.” This refusal demonstrates the relation between dehumanization and discourse, which centers not on dehumanizing discourse itself but a “refusal of discourse that produces dehumanization as a result” (36). The refusal to publish the obituary recognizing the lives and deaths of the two Palestinian families derealizes these lives.
Butler returns to the question of the United States’ response to the violence of 9/11 and the “opportunity” of this trauma. The loss is not only that of lives but of the United States’ “sovereign entitlement.” This is a “grandiose” and “narcissistic” fantasy that must also be mourned as a loss. Rather than mourn the loss of this fantasy, the United States chose to shore it up.
Butler then turns toward how there might be a “way out of the circle of violence altogether” (42). This would entail a world in which “bodily vulnerability is protected without therefore being eradicated and with insisting on the line that must be walked between the two” (42). This may be seen as a new definition of humanism that hinges on shared corporeal vulnerability, but Butler points out that a recognition of vulnerability is dependent on “existing norms of recognition if it is to be attributed to any human subject” (43).
Butler ultimately describes the “foreignness” of the self as ethically charged. While this ignorance of self may initially seem like a problem, Butler is not dismissing the need to know something about oneself as necessary for political action. At the same time, this unknowingness or foreignness of self that may be experienced most profoundly in mourning testifies to a “woundedness” and the fact that responsibility cannot be thought of in isolation. Returning to the United States’ response to 9/11, Butler briefly references Sophocles’s Antigone, highlighting the enormous risks Antigone takes in trying to bury her brother, determined an enemy by Creon; thus, a public mourning goes against his wartime edict. A struggle to resist derealization entails a public refusal of prohibitions on mourning.
“Violence, Mourning, Politics” moves into Butler’s broader discussion of vulnerability, adopting a psychanalytic approach to the “problem” of loss and why a response of aggression often follows an experience of violence. Though Butler sees a difference between the subjectivity of an individual and the subjectivity of a nation, the author contends that a psychoanalytic approach can be useful in thinking about the actions of both.
Firstly, Butler insists on the reality of vulnerability. While people and nations might approach and respond to vulnerability differently, there is no “argument” against it; it is a fact of life.
Chapter 2 moves from Chapter 1’s discussion of the “framing” in response to 9/11, which refused the ethical possibilities and potential of the moment of increased vulnerability, and into a related discussion of the ethical possibilities and potential in the experience of loss and mourning. In doing so, Butler focuses exclusively on the question of “the human,” beginning and ending this chapter with a consideration of how biological humans are excluded from the social and political category of “human” that confers value and mournability. Butler focuses explicitly and exclusively on “the human” and gestures toward a possible redefinition of humanism in relation to the vulnerability shared among all humans.
Of course, the body as the site of vulnerability is not exclusively human, but a condition shared among all creaturely life. The body’s vulnerability is a reality of existence that many species negotiate in ways similar to and different from humans, including the cultural processes of mourning. Many scholars, then, have argued that Butler’s own theory explodes the human exceptionalism that the author assumes.
Vulnerability should not be apprehended as a “weakness” in a traditional sense. In other words, vulnerability is not something to fear or banish. Rather, it is a foundational “resource” for ethical thinking in its exposure, just as the experience of violence itself is a potential ethical resource. The reality of one’s own and others’ innate vulnerability is the foundation for ethics. Butler is particularly interested in social vulnerability and interdependence. While people can experience vulnerability individually, Butler focuses on social vulnerability or the shared vulnerability of being a social being.
This social being-ness is opened up to a profound recognition in the state of mourning, when people become unhinged from their entrenched sense of self and the narratives they tell themselves about their autonomy. People are often lost when they try to determine the exact nature of the loss that has occurred and the exact nature of what one is in the wake of that loss. Like vulnerability, this “unknowingness” may seem to require eradication as quickly as possible, but Butler insists that this is again a charged moment with enormous ethical potential. As in Chapter 1, Butler is interested in experiences of rupture and wounding and their painful potential.
In this essay, Butler establishes Mournability as Recognition of Realized Lives. The discursive prohibition on mourning is more subtle than an explicit and public edict, as in Creon’s to Antigone prohibiting her public mourning and burial of her brother. For example, the obituary functions as a public recognition of lives that have been lost. However, this genre also excludes and polices who can be publicly mourned. This refusal is bound up with the dehumanization of other humans, whose lives have been derealized, and engenders a kind of zombie existence—an existence that is understood as never fully alive and thus never fully dead. Butler’s analysis of prohibitions on public mourning draw attention to those the United States has killed in war and those killed by the United States’ allies, specifically the Israeli killing of Palestinians. This enforced unmournability can be considered more broadly in relation to other systemic violence that refuses mournable deaths, such as in the exploitation of animals killed for food, who could not be eaten if they were mourned.
Butler is interested in the state of vulnerability, of unknowingness, of interdependence that is foundational to humans’ very existence. Rather than attempting to remove oneself from these states of existence or looking for ways to banish vulnerability (as certain technologies desire to achieve), vulnerability should be recognized as intrinsic to the world and ethics. A heightened recognition of one’s vulnerability and that of others, as well as heightened recognition of loss that occurs in mourning, could catalyze ethical thinking and action.
By Judith Butler