74 pages • 2 hours read
Paulo FreireA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more. For select classroom titles, we also provide Teaching Guides with discussion and quiz questions to prompt student engagement.
Summary
Chapter Summaries & Analyses
Key Figures
Themes
Symbols & Motifs
Important Quotes
Essay Topics
Tools
In the Preface, Freire confronts two important challenges to the struggle for liberation: the fear of freedom that inhibits the oppressed from acting to liberate themselves, and the problem of sectarianism, which undermines the possibility of genuine social transformation. He addresses these in turn, noting that the ideas and observations he offers in Pedagogy of the Oppressed derive from his years of experience educating the poor and the middle-class in Latin America.
Freire notes that the oppressed are often concerned that the consciousness-raising, orconscientização, through which the oppressed come to perceive their exploitation will lead to destructive consequences. This is untrue, he asserts, since “by making it possible for people to enter the historical process as responsible Subjects, conscientização enrolls them in the search for self-affirmation and thus avoids fanaticism” (36). The oppressed’s fear of freedom is in reality a defensive measure, “an attempt to achieve security, which [seems preferable] to the risks of liberty” (36). Challenging the culture of domination means confronting the oppressor and destabilizing the tacit social agreement under which they live; this threatens the security of the oppressed, who prefer conformity to liberty.
Genuine freedom, however, is possible only when men and women embrace an existential risk. Freire observes that some of the oppressed are unwilling to risk confronting the reality of their oppression and committing themselves to the struggle for freedom. They mistakenly identify “freedom” with the maintenance of the status quo; “so that if conscientização threatens to place that status quo in question, it thereby seems to constitute a threat to freedom itself” (36). Their fear of freedom, a necessary result of their oppression, impedes the possibility of actual liberation.
Following these remarks, Freire acknowledges that his argument in Pedagogy of the Oppressed may be misinterpreted or rejected by those on both the right and the left. He warns against the dangers of sectarianism in its rightist and leftist versions, and contrasts its closed-mindedness with the realistic and flexible spirit of radicalism. Sectarian politics falsify reality by “mythicizing” it, reducing the ambiguous complexity of our historical experience to a convenient mythological narrative. Radicalism, by contrast, is “nourished by a critical spirit” and unveils the concrete historical foundations of human social organization (37). The radical embraces the objective realityof our existence, enabling them to transform it, while the sectarian is mired in illusion and incapable of grasping the true historical dynamic of reality.
On the political right, the sectarian wishes to freeze time and preserve the conditions of oppression. His leftist counterpart, conversely, imagines history will inevitably culminate in a revolutionary utopia. Both types of sectarian isolate themselves from the evolving historical situation and struggle of the people. The true radical, by contrast, aligns himself with the exploited to serve and encourage their aspirations for transforming the conditions of their existence. Together, they struggle to build a future free from oppression.
Freire holds the pedagogy of the oppressed can only be undertaken by radicals. He concludes the preface with the hope that this pedagogy will result “in the creation of a world in which it will be easier to love” (40).
In the first chapter, Freire introduces the revolutionary context underlying his analysis of oppression as a dehumanizing system of exploitation. After laying out the philosophical ground for the struggle for liberation from oppression, he describes oppression’s dehumanizing effects on both the oppressed and their oppressors. Finally, he explains how education must be remade to motivate and empower the oppressed in their pursuit of emancipation. This new form of education centers on the importance of ongoing dialogue between the oppressed and their educators. Dialogue engages men and women as thinking and acting subjects, rather than treating them as passive receptacles of information. Through dialogue based on mutual trust, the disenfranchised begin to acquire the critical self-awareness and moral commitment necessary to pursue their own liberation.
The pedagogy of the oppressed has two stages.The first deals with the “problem of consciousness” in an oppressive society.It addresses the psychological conditioning of the oppressed and their oppressors that the dehumanizing system of social injustice produces.In this stage, the oppressed become critically conscious of their oppression and commit themselvesto intervene in this situation.The second stage comes after the dominant elite have been expelled from power and the social systemis transformed through revolution.The pedagogy of the oppressed now becomes “a pedagogy of all people in the process of permanent liberation” (54).
Freire frames the struggle for liberation within the philosophical question of what it means to be human. He poses the problem of the oppressed in moral terms, appealing to the Enlightenment idea that to be human is to be free to think and act autonomously. Becoming more fully human is our “vocation” as human beings. It is the birthright of all, regardless of social class, origin, ethnicity, or gender. Though the exploitation of one group by another has been historically commonplace, it is not an unavoidable destiny. Rather, oppression is “the result of an unjust order that engenders violence in the oppressors, which in turn dehumanizes the oppressed” (44). Both oppressor and oppressed are dehumanized by the relationship of exploitation permeating their collective society.
It is natural that the oppressed will take revolutionary action to recover their lost humanity. However, this struggle will have meaning only if the oppressed do not, in turn, become “oppressors of the oppressors, but rather restorers of the humanity of both” (44). Freire contends that only the strength of the weak can bring about the greater humanization of both the weak and the strong. Accordingly, the first task of the pedagogy of the oppressed is to enable “their critical discovery that both they and their oppressors are manifestations of dehumanization” (48).
To explain this dehumanization and describe its effects, Freire analyzes the “false consciousness” that afflicts both oppressor and oppressed and sustains the system of oppression. He then relates how a dialogue-based method of education can overcome the effects of false consciousness and, through the exercise of critical reflection combined with action (“praxis”), enable an authentic struggle for liberation.
Oppression is organized violence; the act of oppression is, in fact, the violence that creates the oppressed. This violence originates in the possessiveness of the oppressor. The oppressor consciousness equates being with having, and in its drive to acquire ever more possessions it treats objects, resources, and people as things to be owned or manipulated for its profit. Moreover, if “being” consists of “having,” those who lack material possessions and social status are reduced to the status of non-being. The domination of the poor by the powerful in all its forms—physical as well as ideological—treats men and women as objects, thus denying them their essential humanity.
Freire contends that the dominant elite will never willingly allow the oppressed to escape their subjugation and enjoy unhindered access to power and material goods: “[A]ny attempt to ‘soften’ the power of the oppressor in deference to the weakness of the oppressed almost always manifests itself in the form of false generosity” (44). This generosity—whether in the form of private charity or state-sponsored welfare—is false because the oppressor must maintain the unjust conditions that enable it. False generosity further dehumanizes those already oppressed, keeping them dependent on their exploiters.
However, as the oppressed attempt to improve their material situation, their effort is undermined by their own false consciousness. Freire observes that the oppressed are often inclined to treat others as they have been treated by their oppressors, rather than fight for true liberation from the oppressive social structure. This is due to the toxic psychological conditioning that saturates oppressive society:
The very structure of their thought has been conditioned by the contradictions of the concrete, existential situation by which they were shaped. Their ideal is to be men; but for them, to be men is to be oppressors (45).
The oppressed cannot think beyond the fundamental duality that has formed their concrete experience, namely, that between ‘oppressor’ and ‘oppressed.’ Once enjoying a taste of greater autonomy and material possessions, they are inclined to act exploitatively as the oppressor acts, modeling their behavior on his.
In this initial stage of the struggle for liberation, the oppressed are trapped within the dichotomy of the two opposing categories (or “contradictions”) that exist in the historical situation of oppression. True liberation involves overcoming the duality of ‘oppressor versus oppressed’ and resolving the problem of oppression in a way that supersedes these antagonistic positions, restoring full humanity to all. As Freire writes, “the solution of this contradiction is born in the labor which brings into the world this new being: no longer oppressor nor oppressed, but human in the process of achieving freedom” (49).
The first step in dismantling the systematic oppression of the poor, then, is to unveil the deep-seated ideologies and patterns of thought that support and sustain it. This stage must address the worldviews and ethics of both the oppressor and the oppressed, as well as their behavior.
Freire identifies five characteristics of the oppressed consciousness that hinder the oppressed in their struggle and accommodate them to their submission. These are the fear of freedom, dual-consciousness, submersion in the oppressive situation, a fatalistic attitude, and self-depreciation.
The fear of freedom is one of the major obstacles to the liberation of the oppressed. Under conditions of oppression, men and women internalize the image of the oppressor and adopt his guidelines for behavior. They are fearful of the risks associated with abandoning those guidelines and assuming responsibility for their freedom. Freedom is not a gift and must be won. At the same time, it is a fundamental value, “the indispensable condition for the quest for human completion” (47). The first step in educating the oppressed to fight for freedom is to help them critically recognize the specific causes of their oppression and discover within themselves the desire to be free.
However, the oppressed suffer from a dual-consciousness that complicates this effort: “although they desire authentic existence, they fear it. They are at one and the same time themselves and the oppressor whose consciousness they have internalized” (47). The dilemma between choosing freedom or the seeming security of the status quo cuts through the hearts and minds of the oppressed. Housing the oppressor within themselves, they are torn “between speaking out or being silent[,]” between being fully themselves or being self-divided (48). Freire insists that the oppressed must come to recognize clearly the oppressor outside themselves, ejecting his internalized image, in order to perceive accurately the totality of their oppression.
This perception is made difficult by the submerged consciousness of the oppressed. The state of oppression absorbs those within it, preventing them from perceiving the reality of oppression objectively. Submerged in the oppressive reality, they adapt to their exploitation, behaving according to the guidelines the oppressor prescribes for them. They are unable to “clearly perceive the ‘order’ which serves the interests of the oppressors whose image they have internalized” (62).As a result of “internalizing” the oppressor, they also, at a certain stage, identify with him.The oppressedare often attracted to the lifestyle of the oppressor and aspire to share it, further exacerbating their dual consciousness.
Furthermore, until they become critically aware of the oppressor and their own conditioning, the oppressed typically display a fatalistic attitude toward their situation. Manipulated ideologically by the oppressor, the oppressed see their social status as part of the “natural” order and their suffering as the will of God. Consequently, they submit passively to an unjust social order, which they accept as a given.
Their passivity is also reinforced by self-depreciation. Denigrated by the oppressor for their supposed laziness, incompetence, and ignorance, the oppressed lack self-esteem.The revolutionary educator must always remain aware of the oppressed’s inclination toward passivity and emotional dependence, therefore, as well as recognize the potential for transformation during their moments of awakening.
Simply recognizing the causes of their oppression is not enough, however, to liberate the oppressed. They must pursue the struggle for liberation through a combination of reflection and revolutionary action, which Freire terms “praxis.” In the praxis, critical reflection and action continually alternate and influence each other. Praxis constantly renews itself; the reflection of the oppressed and their leaders must lead to liberating action (reflection itself is a form of action), and the results of action must become the object of critical reflection.
Genuine liberation for alldoes not mean that the formerly oppressed now become oppressors of those who previously exploited them, however. Freire acknowledges that certain restraints need to be placed on the formerly powerful to prevent them from reassuming that position, but this does not constitute oppression.However, even when the social structure of oppression has been overcome, “the former oppressors do not feel liberated” by a more egalitarian society, but “genuinely consider themselves to be oppressed” in turn (57).Any restriction on their former way of life, even for the common good, seems to them a violent infringement of their rights.
This way of thinking is rooted in their experience as a dominant class.Materialistic and exploitative, the oppressor tends to transform everything around him into an object of his domination.Even the idea of “humanity” is reduced to a “thing,” which he possesses with an exclusive right.
Feeling entitled to his privileged position, the oppressor is angered by what he sees as the oppressed’s “ingratitude” for the “generosity” shown to them.Accordingly, he redoubles his efforts to control the oppressed through manipulation and suppression. Freire, quoting the psychoanalyst Erich Fromm, argues that this “in-animating” of the oppressed reveals the sadistic tendency of the oppressor consciousness.In trying to suffocate the natural vitality and desire for freedom among the oppressed, the oppressor revealshisown necrophilia, or death-loving instinct.
Freire rejects the claims of the powerful that the oppressed are wantonly violent, suggesting that their effort to overcome the dehumanization of oppression is in reality an act of love.The oppressor loves only himself; he initiates the terror under which the oppressed suffer.By contrast, the oppressed respond to this violence out of a righteous desire to be more fully human.Since the oppressors’ dehumanization of the oppressed dehumanizes themselves as well, by stripping away the oppressors’ “power to dominate and suppress, [the oppressed] restore to the oppressors the humanity they had lost in the exercise of oppression” (56). Thus, it is the historical mission of the oppressed to achieve this liberation of all humankind.
The education of the oppressed, accordingly, cannot proceed by monologues, communiqués, propagandistic slogans, or other “instruments of domestication” (65). These tools of the oppressor objectify his listeners. Rather, the oppressed must be their own example in the struggle for liberation and accept full responsibility for that struggle.Revolutionary education must consist of dialogue respecting the knowledge and experience of the oppressed, since “trusting the people is the indispensable precondition for revolutionary change” (60). Dialogical education expresses the consciousness and validates the autonomy of the oppressed, both of which are necessary for their struggle for freedom (54).
Pedagogy of the Oppressed is one of the foundational works of critical pedagogy, a philosophy and method of education that views teaching as an inherently political act, and the goal of education as liberation from oppressive social conditions. The book was published in Portuguese in 1968; English and Spanish translations that greatly expanded its reach appeared in 1970.Over a million copies have been sold worldwide since, making it one of the most popular and influential books on education published in the twentieth century. Freire is considered by many to be the most influential proponent and educational theorist of critical pedagogy.
The argument of the book derives from Freire’s experience teaching literacy to impoverished peasants and urban laborers in Brazil and Chile from the late 1940s through the mid-1960s. In 1964, Freire’s literacy projects in Brazil came to an end after a military coup backed by the U.S. government ousted Brazilian President JoãoGoulart. Freire was imprisoned briefly, then lived in exile in Bolivia and Chile for several years, where he worked for agrarian reform and the Food and Agriculture Organization of the United Nations. In 1980, he returned to live in Brazil, where he died in 1997.
Freire’s analysis of oppression and the “false consciousness” it promotes is heavily influenced by Marxist and post-colonial thought, as well as by thecritical theory developed by members of the Frankfurt School of social research during the 1930s. Freire also draws upon the work of the psychoanalyst/philosopher Erich Fromm, whose distinction between “necrophily,” or life-negating, and “biophily,” or life-affirming, attitudes and behaviors helps Freire illuminate the oppressor and revolutionary mentalities, respectively.
To the student unfamiliar with Marx’s terminology, idea of historical materialism, and critique of capitalism, Freire’s language and argument in Pedagogyof theOppressed can seem difficult and overly abstract. Marx’s view of history as the embodiment of successive phases of class conflict reworks his predecessor G. W. F. Hegel’s idea of the dialectic. The dialectic is a dynamic structure of historical progression in which two opposing forces clash with each other and are ultimately superseded by a third configuration that resolves (or overcomes) the opposition of the original two. This third stage serves as a new term in the continual unfolding of the dialectic, prompting its own contradiction and future overcoming. Freire’s argument in Pedagogy consistently refers to the dialectic and sets of dichotomies—oppressor versus oppressed, subject versus object, reflection versus action, etc.—that need to be overcome (or unified) within history to achieve authentic liberation for all.
In the Preface, Freire frames the question of human freedom in dialectical terms, citing Hegel: “It is solely by risking life that freedom is obtained . . .” (36). Freire refers to the passage known as the “Master-Slave Dialectic” in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Mind, which presents an account of how self-consciousness originates.For Hegel, consciousness of one’s self as a free being is mediated through an ‘other’ in a dialectical process that involves a struggle to the death.The development of self-consciousness is achieved through an asymmetrical encounter between two conscious beings, each vying for the other’s recognition in a struggle for domination. To recognize oneself, and be recognized, as an independent, self-conscious subject, capable of freely-willed action and critical self-reflection, one must first risk one’s own existence. Freire returns to this Hegelian model of social interaction several times in Pedagogy.
For the oppressed to be recognized as fully human, they must recognize themselves as the products of oppression and exploitation, understanding the causes of their oppression and seeing the oppressor outside themselves.This is the object of conscientização, the process of developing critical awareness of the social reality through reflection and action. (Roughly equivalent to “consciousness-raising,” Freire’s term is usually translated as “conscientization” in English).
The age-old philosophical problem of the relationship between subject and objectalso looms large in Freire’s argument. The oppressed’s struggle for freedom and fuller humanity is a struggle to transform their objectification by the oppressor into the self-affirmation of subjects who know and act. The oppressed can be agents in transforming the world because history, for Freire, is a possibility, not pre-determined. By means of conscientização and the praxis, men and women realize the possibility of making history consciously, not simply participating passively in the historical process. Both praxis, the combination of reflection and conscious action, and conscientização, to which it is related, bring the subjective and objective aspects of reality into a unified totality. World and action are intimately interdependent, and action is not properly human unless it is unified with critical reflection.
Freire takes up the subject/object problem again when he addresses the Marxist question of what determines human consciousness. Is consciousness formed solely by the concrete, external conditions in which men and women live—the socio-economic, political, religious, cultural forms dominant in a given society? Freire argues that human consciousness is formed to some extent by these conditions, but it is also able to think about and act upon them, thus transforming them.
The abstract quality and scarcity of concrete examples in Freire’s argument has drawn criticism. His division of society into opposing groups of oppressors and oppressed, for instance, assumes a clear and sharp division between the two groups that may be overly simplistic considering the complexity of human social organization. Similarly, his claim that restraining the former oppressors to prevent them from reassuming power is not itself oppressive seems a debatable assertion.